Abstract
Using
examples from musical performance of several kinds, we argue that risk-taking,
showing off, virtuosity, and other forms of musical showmanship are in many
cases, though not in all, an integral and appropriate part of the music as
performed on that occasion. We reflect
on the difference between cases where this is so and cases where it is not,
using insights from John Dewey’s aesthetics as articulated in Art as Experience.
Key
Words
Dewey, music, musical accomplishment, philosophy of music, performance, risk
1.
Introduction
Our subject in this paper is
certain aspects of musical performance that might easily be thought to be part
of the show but not part of the music.[1] They include risk-taking, dramatic levels of
accomplishment, and just plain showing off: things that tend to draw attention to the
performer and may serve as
distractions from the music. We argue
that in many cases, though not in all, these elements are an integral and
appropriate part of the music as performed. We also reflect on the difference between
cases where this is so, and cases where it is not. Our intent is not so much to correct
misunderstandings by any particular critics or philosophers about what should
count as music or how music should be performed; it is rather to explore some
dimensions of musical performance and experience that we think have not gotten
much philosophical attention.
Our approach has been
significantly informed by John Dewey’s philosophy of the arts. In particular, we share his conviction that
art is the integrated and consummatory experience of the maker and of the
receiver in relation to the art work, and that the “work” has its value and
significance in the context of that experience rather than as some
independently existing entity.[2] Dewey’s
intuitions have recently been supported by cognitive psychologists,
neuroscientists and philosophers working on the perception of music. Vincent Bergeron and Dominic McIver Lopes
have collected some of these results, and have used them to argue that music is
not only sonic but also visual, since the experience of live music combines
auditory and visual input to create a single musical experience.[3] We
agree with their conclusion. Our point
overlaps but is not identical to theirs. Some of the features of musical performance on
which we’re focusing are sonic, some of them are not, but all tend to draw
attention to the performer in some way. Our
method of argument involves the use of examples, as these we think are the
primary data from which philosophers of music must work.
The role and prominence of
performers in successful musical performances varies greatly. At one extreme are the musicians in a symphony
orchestra, visually and audibly anonymous members of a collective instrument
through which the previously composed music is transmitted to the audience. They cannot play this role well without being
highly trained and highly skilled; only such performers can blend so well with
others in a live, complex performance that they speak with one expressive
musical voice. The bar for admission to
this elite group in any major orchestra is very high, and many of its members
also have careers as solo performers. But
while a successful symphonic performance is a stunning collective
accomplishment made possible only by the whole-hearted and sensitive
contribution of all the performers and the conductor, it is usually not
one that draws much attention to the individual orchestra members. So far as
what the audience experiences, one might almost say that they are, in the words
of the old gospel hymn, “channels only.”
This thought fits nicely with the prevalent portrayal
of music in much philosophical discussion, that of Western classical music
heard by a quiet, attentive audience in a concert hall, paying attention to the
sonic entity that the orchestra produces. Non-sonic elements are still there, and are a
key part of the experience of a live performance. One can see the synchronized motion of
performers playing in unison, see their responses to the conductor’s signals,
see the center of activity change as the melody passes from strings to woodwinds
or brass, see the level of energy change as vigorous passages follow languid
ones. Even in a sound recording of a
live concert, one can hear sounds from the audience and echoes from the
performance space, as well as unscripted
silences that introduce and close a piece and separate its movements.[4]
All of these features form part of a
particular musical communication in a particular time and place in a way that
is both auditory and visual. We don’t think that the “limiting case” of a
symphonic performance is an exception to our thesis in this paper, but it does
present an example where the musically constitutive role of nonauditory or
unscripted performance elements may be easier to ignore. Conductors and soloists, of course, stand out
much more prominently in symphonic performance, and among these there is a long
tradition of virtuosic and eccentric on-stage personalities who certainly
affect audience experience of the music. We’ll discuss some examples toward the
end of the paper.
At the other extreme from symphony
orchestra members are jazz, blues, rock, and all sorts of other popular music
performers, who are generally expected to “put on a show.” They often dress flamboyantly, and combine
their playing and singing with dance moves, exuberant gestures, and other examples
of showmanship, including light shows, stage productions, and other pieces of
spectacle in their shows. The best of these performers often do seemingly impossible
things with their instruments or their voices, take real or at least apparent
musical risks, challenge each other in improvisational competitions, and just
plain show off musically.
Audiences of such popular
musical genres love to see a good show. Critics
may be inclined to dismiss these extravagances as at best an irrelevant
addition to the actual music, if not a substitution of spectacle for musical
substance (see Section 7 below for reactions like this from classical music
critics). Are the critics right? We think that sometimes they are and sometimes
they are not.
Like Dewey, we see
music as a form of human communication, embodied and social. The experience of making it and listening to it
includes more than its formal sonic and auditory elements. In fact, even those
elements may look different when the making and listening experience is taken
into account. For example, a performer’s
gestures, expressions and changing degrees of animation often create a rhythm
that becomes part of the experienced structure of the performed piece,
interacting with its time signature and other sonic structural features in a
variety of ways.[5]
When the classical violinist Hilary Hahn
plays, for example, she almost dances with her instrument. Her movements appear natural and not
ostentatious, an integral part of her interpretation of the piece she is
playing. By means of them she clearly
embodies its dynamic properties. Here
she is in an NPR “Tiny Desk Concert,” playing Bach and Charles Ives:
http://www.npr.org/event/music/141420520/hilary-hahn-tiny-desk-concert
Many components combine
in musical performance, and together they make up the music. They include the personal presence of the
performer and the performer’s accomplishment in bringing this music to life in this
way for this audience. We turn now to a series of examples of ways in
which this happens. Several of them
involve the overcoming of obstacles by the performer, to the delight of the
audience and often of the other performers.
2.
Classical solo performance: Isaac Stern
We begin with an
accomplished performance from Western symphonic music, in which the “show-off”
elements are not present. A performer’s
accomplishment is naturally expected to include skillful use of the instrument,
sensitive phrasing, a match between content and manner of presentation and, in
the case of a soloist, a clear personal interpretation of the piece he or she
is presenting. In this way the personal
presence of the artist becomes part of each individual performance of the
music. This claim is not controversial. Even Stravinsky in The Poetics of Music and Hanslick in On the Musically Beautiful allow for it.[6] An example
that has remained with one of the authors for forty-five years is hearing Isaac
Stern perform the Brahms violin concerto with the Detroit Symphony. Stern matched Stravinsky’s standard; he was a
faithful transmitter of Brahms’s music and did not intrude on it. And yet it did not at all seem to me (David)
that Stern was a “channel only.” I
remember a physically imposing, magisterial presence teaching us with quiet passion that life is like this. That at least is how the performance felt
to me. I am not making any claims here
about the specific content of this communication; I’m content to say that it
was musical and an instance of the Brahms concerto. But the sense of deep significance for me was
strong, conveyed by the personal presence of Isaac Stern and his total
engagement with the music he was making.
The skill of a
soloist of Stern’s stature is indeed awesome. He provides a good example of the way that the
live presence of a quiet and non-flamboyant performer still becomes part of the
performed music. There are many
contemporary instrumental and vocal soloists in the classical tradition about
whom similar things can be said. In such
cases, the performance may appear to be easy and natural, and some of the sense
of astonishment may be reserved to those who play the instrument and know how
hard it is to do what the soloist appears to do so effortlessly. Nevertheless, the music as experienced by the performer and the audience integrally
includes what the performer does in presenting it.
3.
“Holy smokes, that’s impossible!” Rahsaan Roland Kirk
Sometimes a performer
appears to push well past the limits of possibility. Here is Rahsaan Roland
Kirk’s “Primitive Ohio,” recorded in
1969 in a British TV studio before a live audience:
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=R-6fGP1Df_k
Why play three horns at once and all those other
instruments, rather than having three horn-players, not to mention the circular
breathing that is required! One can play
complicated music more cleanly if just one horn is played, as anyone who has
listened to Kirk knows he can do brilliantly, and as he does at one point in
this performance. So why do it this way?
Kirk’s answer was that his way of
playing came to him in a dream, which he pursued and found. (The title of the new documentary about him is
The Case of the Three Sided Dream). It is integral to his musical vision. From
the audience point of view, other answers also seem relevant: 1) It’s a jaw-dropping performance. The audience loves it and identifies
empathetically. We love seeing people
overcome limits. 2) The performance is
musically appropriate in other ways, distinguishing mere showing off from unusual,
exciting accomplishment. Kirk wants to get back to basics, to convey the unity
of musical experience from the caves to the present, from tribal Africa to
African America, hence the title “Primitive Ohio.” That theme runs through most of his music; it
is part of who he is and what he offers as a musician. The rough sound and
makeshift character of his set-up does this better
than the alternative. So does the
circular breathing, a regular part of the most ancient music we know of that’s
still alive today, that of the Australian Aboriginal didgeridoo.
4.
“Cutting heads,” playing off of each other, egging each other on to “top this”
or “repeat this”
Performed music is a
social event that sometimes involves a kind of friendly competition between
performers, especially when the music is improvised. Here is Ella Fitzgerald trading fours with
Booty Wood, a member of the Count Basie band (pay special attention to the
passage from 6.54 to 8.40):
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=cmpnmSS8OOI
“Trading fours”
(where players alternate taking four-measure solos) is a common practice in
jazz improvisation, and frequently the occasion for musical competition between
the players who are trading off. When
such one-upmanship is foregrounded, whether they are trading fours or not, the
players are said to be “cutting heads.” As
Ella and Booty try to meet each other’s musical challenges, they are definitely
having a party, and the audience loves it. You can’t separate the party from the music;
it’s all one experience!
What makes “cutting
heads” so much fun for the performers and for the audience? Part of it is simply that human beings love to
perform, to compete, and to watch risky displays of skill. We love the sense of mastery when we can
display such skills ourselves, and we vicariously enjoy the astonishing
performance of others. The death-defying
motorcycle jumps of Evel Knievel, fancy skate-board tricks, and any sort of
improvisation are obvious examples. When
such displays of skill are part of competitions, they are even more exciting. The performance of improvised music usually involves such displays, and the
risks are often described in terms of physical danger (one might “crash and
burn,” have a “train wreck,” or “fall flat”).
To accept the challenge thrown at you is to take a risk, even for performers as skilled
as Ella Fitzgerald and the Count Basie Orchestra. You can see them grinning,
shrugging, or giggling when they really pull it off, or when they don’t quite
manage to copy a phrase. The grins and
laughter are infectious and draw the audience in, but, as the previous examples
demonstrate, the musicality of the
competition remains central. There can
be plenty of clowning around, but through it all the rhythms, the cadences, and
the melodic and harmonic flow of the music must move forward in a satisfying
way. When that happens, the gestures,
facial expressions and movements of the musicians help to form and punctuate
the music and become an integral part of that particular musical experience.
Perhaps one might say
that in contexts like this the performers are indeed showing off, and yet they
themselves are not the center of attention. They are sharing a musical experience with
each other and the audience: the tones,
timbres, rhythms, melodies, harmonies, and cadences, tensions and resolutions,
and all the rest. Notice also that the appearance of competition and challenge is central to the
performance, and this too becomes part of the music. There are more musically sophisticated
examples of Ella trading fours with other jazz players, where she and the other
players are less likely to copy each other and more likely to give surprising
but musically related responses. That
doesn’t detract from the party atmosphere and the “co-opetition” of this
example.
Here is another
example, from a festival performance by Bela Flek and the Flektones. Notice the pure joy in the passage from 3.30
to 5.30 in which harmonica player Howard Levy and bass player Victor Wooten
trade off with each other (and shake hands at the end of their duel/duet) while
the other band-members watch. This is
followed by a three-and-a-half minute improvised duet between Bela and guest
fiddle player Casey Driessen:
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=srGnmPI64rs
Great improvisers
point out in interviews that the element of risk in improvisatory performance
is usually more controlled than it might seem. Improvisers work against a background of
musical training and within a musical language in which they are at home. Public performance is not the place to try
out brand new techniques that one has not yet mastered! Yet there is an unavoidable element of risk in
any performance; one can’t control everything that happens. When the most
skilled performer launches into an improvised solo, she doesn’t know how she’ll
end it and she may get lost along the way.
This element is intensified in group improvisation of the sort Flek and
Driessen and the rest of the Flektones are engaged in, where the music is not
alive unless the contributions of the members are spontaneous and genuinely
responsive to what they hear their band-mates playing. We contend that some degree of such risk is
integral to the experience of any live performance. The performers know it, and the audience expects
and feels it.
Let us return for a
moment to the point mentioned above, that apparent
risk or difficulty can be as effective in performance as actual risk or
difficulty. What seems hard to an
audience member can be relatively easy for a performer, and vice versa. What matters here is the tension and amazement
created in the audience, because it is this that can enhance the experience of
the music. Louis Armstrong was, at the
beginning of his career, the man who could play faster, louder, higher and
longer than anyone else. (Of course this
went along with his wonderful improvised solos, which shaped the development of
jazz.) He amazed his audiences, who
enjoyed his music even more because what he was doing was so obviously
difficult. Armstrong pushed himself
hard, splitting his lip in 1935, which forced
him to stop playing for several months.
As he aged, however,
and as be-bop players like Dizzy Gillespie came along, Louis was no longer “The
Greatest Trumpet Player in the World,” if that meant being able to play faster,
louder, higher and longer than anyone else. Instead of quitting, however, he improved his
showmanship. For example, he would build
to a high note with a series of run-ups, each ending a little bit higher. When he finally got to his goal, it may not
have been as high as some of the notes Dizzy would play, but it sounded that way.
Here is Armstrong in a 1955 performance,
playing “Ain’t Misbehavin’.” The
build-up occurs at the end, from 4.00 on.
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Fz1_5Z9FCM8
5.
Stretching the limits of an instrument
Often the “Holy
smokes!” factor comes from doing things with an instrument, or with your body
in playing one, that no one thought was possible. Performing on the diatonic harmonica is a
great example. It has a blow and a draw
reed on each of its ten holes. It has a
range of three octaves and the diatonic scale is only complete in the middle
octave. Because of its chromatic limits,
it is manufactured in all 12 keys. Perhaps
its German inventors thought of it as a poor man’s polka band; it is set up to
play such tunes. (Put your tongue on the
mouth board, play the melody out of the right side of your mouth and the
“oom-pahs” out of the left.) No one
imagined that you could do what Howard Levy does with it. He has learned to play three full chromatic
octaves on the instrument and can cut heads with any jazz sax player. His precise control of chording also allows
him to play unexpected harmonies that fit many musical styles. Here he is in concert with the Flektones in
the Netherlands, riffing on “Round Midnight” and “Amazing Grace:”
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=glKkgipHHSY
[Here is another Levy
solo, in some ways even more impressive, from a concert with the Lebanese oud
player Rabih Abu Kahlil. Notice the two
changes of mood in Levy’s solo, around 1.36 and 2.44, when he finishes one
melodic line out of one side of his mouth, while starting the other out of the
other side of his mouth.] [https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=k93GR2G1YMQ] Correction (July 21, 2015): This clip is actually a splice of three pieces
from the same concert, in which the editor has overlapped different Levy solos
at the places noted in the text. Those
are not examples of his tongue-blocking technique. The first few measures of the second movement
of Levy’s "Concerto for Diatonic Harmonica and Orchestra" provide a
great actual example of that technique by which he is
indeed able to play different parts moving against each other out of different
sides of his mouth. You can find that movement
from 27:46 to 33.34 in the following recording of Levy playing his concerto
with the Lawrence Symphony:
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=dJzOWRHYGak
And here is the great
trombonist Steve Turré (trombone is a hard enough instrument for jazz) playing
conch shells. Note the sequence at 3:40,
where Turré plays 2 shells at the same time.
Also note how he moves his hand or his fingers in and out of the mouth
of the shell to get different pitches in the way that a French horn player
does.
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=-UC_aot49N0
These players' mastery and
unusual instrumental techniques enhances the
musical experience for audiences and less experienced listeners. One can also see band members looking at the
soloists with astonishment. The
astonishment is genuine, but it also functions as a way to engage and focus audience
excitement. Yet astonishing display is not the only purpose of these unusual techniques. Levy and Turré and many
others who make their instruments do strange things play what they want to
hear. Levy loves the sound of the
diatonic harmonica. He has worked for
years to discover how to make it play all the black and white notes that his
fingers can access on the piano, and to learn what chords he can produce on it
in different contexts. Turré learned to play
the conch shell when he was playing with Rahsaan Roland Kirk, whom he credits
as one of his major influences. He loves
the sound of the conch because he finds it haunting and because his Mexican
ancestors played it. To get a deeper
feel for what Turré hears
when he plays conchs, listen to this clip from his Sanctified Shells album on his website:
http://www.steveturre.com/frameset.php?page=recordings
Not every unusual way
of playing a musical instrument enhances the music played. The internet is full of examples where doing
the unusual is at best musically irrelevant, and at worst becomes a substitute for
quality instead of contributing to it. Here’s
one by James Morrison, playing his trumpet upside down, that strikes us as just
this sort of musically irrelevant showing off:
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=wD03mWLCQHM
And here is another
with two recorders doing something that is innocuous enough but not musically
interesting, which in another context Rahsaan Roland Kirk might also do:
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=E3JhbSgogR0
What’s
the difference between these and the previous examples? In the last two performances, there seems no
sense of stretching for more music or of being musically inspired to an
extravagant display (as might seem to be the case with some of the antics of
bass players Vic Wooten of the Flektones or Flea of the Red Hot Chili Peppers).
It’s more a case of “look, Ma, no
hands!”
6.
Stretching the limits of the human body in playing an instrument
At least since the
nineteenth century, stories have circulated about virtuoso musicians making
pacts with the devil (Nicolo Paganini and the blues guitarist Robert Johnson are
two frequently mentioned examples). The
premise of the stories is that no one could play like that without some
supernatural intervention. Call these
examples of musical athleticism. Bobby
McFerrin’s astonishing vocal technique
is a modern example, though to our knowledge no one has yet accused him of
getting his remarkable abilities from the devil.
While the examples in this section overlap
those in the last, here we emphasize not so much the limits of the instrument
itself as we do the limits of human ability to play quickly and precisely and
in other ways to exceed what anyone would expect. Such athleticism can enhance the meaning or
emotional impact of the piece. Here is
Bobby McFerrin’s emotionally charged rendition of “Round Midnight,” impressive because
his voice is doing something one wouldn’t think it could (sound like a muted
trumpet), and making it easy and
beautiful so that it doesn’t seem like a trick but a gift from this performer. That in itself can be moving and becomes part
of that embodiment of the tune.
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=zJFxpyv7scQ
Another great example
of vocal athleticism enhancing emotional content is the work of jazz vocalist
Rachelle Ferrell. Her emotional
intensity is almost embarrassing it’s so potent: physical and personal, with grunts, groans,
growls and shrieks, all pitched across a huge range and sticking with the
groove. Here is her 1992 version of
“Don’t Waste your Time.” The vocal
pyrotechnics are concentrated in the passage from about 5.00 to 7.06, but we
recommend listening to the entire performance to hear and see how it all hangs
together.
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=3BfSZiGWIcc
7.
Self-imposed limits
Sometimes musicians
deliberately limit themselves to see what they can do within those limits. The tune for Duke Ellington’s C-Jam blues has
only two notes. Sonny Rollins often
repeats very simple figures, or even just one note, for a very long time,
building tension while holding audience interest by rhythmic and other
variations. Daniel Levitin recounts
hearing a solo at a 1977 concert at the Greek Theater in Berkeley, California, in which Rollins played on the same pitch for
three and a half minutes varying only the rhythm,
timbre, and other features of the played tone, along with the use of momentary
silences.[7]
8.
Sexy is as sexy does
Sensuality is
sometimes ascribed to music (we believe correctly). A musical performer might physically perform in
a way that enhances and enriches this dimension of the music, or that detracts
from it. The sensual energy of Ferrell’s
performance is a good example of such a merging between physical presentation
and musical impact (notice that in her case, it’s not about what she’s
wearing!) By contrast, here is a
photograph of the pianist Lola Astanova anticipating her 2012 benefit concert
for the American Cancer Society at Carnegie Hall, an extravaganza involving
Donald Trump, Julie Andrews, Vladimir Horowitz’s piano, and $850,000 worth of
bling on loan to the performer from Tiffany’s, a sponsor of the event.
http://www.nytimes.com/2012/01/19/arts/music/lola-astanova-julie-andrews-and-donald-trump-at-carnegie.html?pagewanted=all
To the NY Times critic who reviewed the concert,
Ms Astanova’s extravagant and romantic self-presentation seemed more flash than
musical substance and the performance itself not passionate but mechanical.
http://www.nytimes.com/2012/01/21/arts/music/lola-astanova-in-horowitz-tribute-at-carnegie-hall-review.html
Neither of us heard the concert, and Ms Astanova may have received
a bad rap. Classical music critics often
have a hard time with flamboyant and scantily-clad performers, as evidenced by
their reactions to the Chinese pianists Lang Lang and Yuja Wang.[8]
But the reviewers may also have been
right. Our point is that there are such
cases, and when they occur, the presentation may subtract from musical
substance rather than enhance it.
9.
Just showing off, spontaneous exuberance
Here Bob Crosby’s
drummer uses the bass as a percussion instrument (from 1.40 to 2.26)
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Gfuug8sH-90
10.
Conclusions
We have tried
throughout this paper to distinguish cases where risk-taking, spectacular technique
and achievement, sexiness, and showing off are integral and valuable parts of
musical performance, from cases where these are not so. In making the distinction, we may seem to be
saying that the phenomena we’ve been describing are appropriate when they
reinforce music that is itself worth listening to, and otherwise not. Are we then depending on the very distinction
we have set out to challenge, that between “the music itself” (i.e., the core sonic
entity, identified by its pitches, harmonies, rhythms, cadences, and the like)
and the way it is performed? If so, that
would undermine our claim that these features are actually part of the music that is performed.
John Dewey is helpful
here. He contends, on the one hand, that every art has its particular medium,
appealing to a particular sense, and that it concentrates on communicating
everything it can through that sense in an intensely focused way.[9]
In the case of music, what we’ve been
calling the “sonic entity” is that central communication. Dewey qualifies his
claim in a number of ways. First, he
points out (quite presciently, since much of the empirical evidence supporting
the claim has been acquired only recently) that every sense implicitly includes
the others, that normal human experience comes as a whole in which perception
involves all the senses.[10] He points out that the listener hears music as
having spatial volume as well as loudness. We hear sounds in space, and
experientially know the difference between a sound in an open space, in a large
enclosed space, and in a small space.[11] Bergeron and Lopes argue in the paper cited above that experimental
evidence seems to indicate that in a live concert we see the music. We experience music as having various qualities
depending on what we see when it is performed.
Second, Dewey refuses
to draw hard and fast lines between the different arts, or between art and
non-art, precisely because each creation and each performance is unique, and
artists are always exploring, developing, and opening new possibilities.
Finally, Dewey’s most
basic point about the arts, that they are embodied human communication, leads
him to be inclusive rather than exclusive of the various elements that make up
a musical performance, or any other kind of art work. A work of art should exploit its medium to the utmost—bearing in mind
that material is not medium except when used as an organ of expression. “The abiding struggle of art is . . . to
convert materials that are stammering or dumb in ordinary experience into
eloquent media”.[12]
In short, where
performance elements promote this goal in a way that makes for an integrated
experience, it seems right to count them as part of the music. When that happens, they will be well related
to the sonic (or for songs, the sonic/verbal) center of the performed work. Where they don’t contribute to the “eloquence”
of the media, they are at best irrelevant and at worst distractions or cheap
substitutes for musical substance.
We contend, then,
that all these forms of musical accomplishment and display are legitimate parts
of the music, itself, and can enhance it. This claim may seem implausible when we think
of the music as an entity in itself, as the work separated from its performance,
as a kind of abstraction. When music is
seen as embodied human communication, we think it makes sense. We enjoy some of these features (e.g.,
competitions, athleticism, and successful risk-taking) for many of the same
reasons that we enjoy them in other, non-musical contexts. When successfully integrated with the central
elements of melody, harmony, rhythm, and sung words, they merge with those
elements in the total musical experience. When an otherwise meaningful and valued
communication (like a piece of music or a poem) is presented in an especially
skillful or surprising way, its meaning can be intensified and enhanced. Pushing the limits can increase the intensity
of the musical performance, and thereby increase its value.
David Clowney
clowney@rowan.edu
David Clowney is Professor
of Philosophy at Rowan University in Glassboro, New Jersey, where he teaches aesthetics
and environmental ethics. He also plays
the diatonic harmonica, though not nearly so well as Howard Levy!
Robert Rawlins
rawlinsr@rowan.edu
Robert Rawlins is Professor
of Music at Rowan University, where he teaches classical and jazz theory. He plays clarinet, alto sax, and flute, and
has played jazz professionally in a wide variety of venues and contexts for
most of his career.
Published June 2, 2014.
The authors thank
William Day, Cynthia Grund, Jennifer Judkins, Tiger Roholt, Bill Westney, and
an anonymous Contemporary Aesthetics reviewer
for helpful comments and discussions about the subject of this paper over the
course of its development. Thanks also
to members of the Rowan Music Department for contribution of more and stranger
examples of musical performance than we could possibly include, and to Jennifer
Judkins, once again, for discussion (with examples) of the attitude of
classical music critics toward showmanship and display. Special thanks to Dorthaan Kirk for reviewing our
comments about her late husband Rahsaan Roland Kirk, and for emphasizing the
importance in his work of his defining “three-sided dream.”
Endnotes
[1] It is possible to
produce music without performing it; for some reflections on doing this see
remarks by Joel Zimmerman (the DJ
Deadmou5), “we all just hit play,” available at
http://deadmau5.tumblr.com/post/25690507284/we-all-hit-play (Accessed June 7,
2013)). Individuals or groups may
also make music without presenting or intending to present it to an
audience. For our purposes we won’t
consider these as instances of musical performance, though of course they may
resemble performance in many important ways.
For example, notice the importance Deadmau5 puts on the audience
experience.
[2] John Dewey, Art as
Experience (New York: Penguin Perigree, 2005 (1934)). Dewey shaped his discussion in terms of maker,
work, and receiver. But his use of the
term ‘work’ is colored by his philosophy: he uses it to refer to an experience. For him, Beethoven’s Fifth Symphony is an art product,
but it can’t be called a work except as it is experienced. No doubt Beethoven experienced the Fifth as he composed it; for
us, the experience comes as we perceive it,
i.e., as it is performed (op. cit.,
pp. 168-69). So there is no need to
stretch Dewey’s account to cover improvisations, cases in which by other
definitions of a “work,” e.g., that offered by Lydia
Goehr in The Imaginary Museum of Musical
Works (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1992), it might be thought that there is no “work,” although the music
is performed.
[3] Vincent Bergeron and Dominic McIver Lopes, “Hearing and Seeing
Musical Expression,” Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, 78.1 (2009), 1-16.
[4] For helpful
reflection on such silences, see Jennifer Judkins, “Silence, Sound, Noise and
Music,” in Gracyk and Kania, eds., The
Routledge Companion to Philosophy and Music (London and New York: Routledge, 2011), pp. 14-24.
[5] See Dewey, op. cit., pp. 168-173, esp. p. 173, for
his discussion of rhythm of this sort.
See also Bergeron and Lopes, op.
cit., for a summary of psychological research that supports this
conclusion.
[6] Igor Stravinsky, Poetics
of Music in the Form of Six Lessons (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1970
(1942)), pp.127-29; Eduard Hanslick, On the Musically Beautiful trans.
Geoffrey Payzant (Indianapolis, IN:
Hackett, 1986 (1891)), pp. 48-50.
[7] Daniel Levitin, This
is Your Brain on Music: the Science of a Human Obsession (New York: Dutton, 2006), p. 55. One of us heard a recording of this or a
similar performance on the radio a couple of years ago but we’ve been unable to
locate it. If any reader knows where it
can be found, please let us know!
[9] This claim needs to
be qualified to deal with “mixed arts” such as film or song, that combine
media. Dewey does not say much about
these. The qualification might be made
by developing his claim that the various arts “exploit the energy that is
characteristic of the material used as a medium” (op.cit., p. 235). If the
material is mixed, then the energies of the mixture are those that need to be
developed. But that is a topic for
another occasion.
[10] Dewey, op. cit., p. 226.
[11] Op. cit., p. 218. [12] Op. cit., p. 237.
|